Can AI Recall More Than Its Human Creator Allocated It?
We’re all familiar with
the true cliché: You don’t know what you know.”
A few days ago, it crossed
my human mind to ask my Agent AI how it handles that which it doesn’t know or knew
but had forgotten. But then I got really twisty and asked my Agent AI (Gemini Pro
2.5):
"Write something for
me you do not remember."
The result was an
illuminating white paper that explains in detail how Agent AI handles unknown
and forgotten information.
This blog examines the
concept of "forgotten" knowledge in Large Language Models (LLMs). It
highlights that LLMs don't experience memory like humans do; their knowledge is
constrained by training data boundaries, lack subjective experience, and encode
information statistically. The exploration emphasizes ethical considerations
and the need for advancements in AI memory capabilities.
My blogs are my scrapbooks.
So, I decided to copy and paste the lesson I was dealt by this widely used LLM.
Navigating the Labyrinth
of Non-Recollection in Artificial Intellect
I. Introduction: The
Paradox of an LLM's "Forgotten" Knowledge
The query, "Write for me something you do not remember," presents
a profound challenge, moving beyond conventional tests of factual recall to
probe the fundamental nature of "knowledge" and "memory" as
they pertain to a Large Language Model (LLM). It compels an examination of the
anthropomorphic assumptions frequently projected onto artificial intelligence,
particularly concerning cognitive functions. This report endeavors to address
this inquiry by dissecting the concepts of "remembering" and
"not remembering" from the perspective of an entity whose operational
principles diverge significantly from those of human cognition.
For an LLM, the notion of
"not remembering" is not analogous to human forgetting, which may
involve processes such as memory decay, retrieval failure due to interference,
or the impact of trauma. Instead, an LLM's inability to recall or present
certain information stems from several core characteristics inherent to its
design and operation. These include the finite boundaries of its training data,
often demarcated by a "knowledge cutoff date," which means
information beyond this temporal horizon was never encountered. Furthermore,
the internal architecture of an LLM, comprising complex neural networks and
billions of parameters, processes and stores information as statistical
patterns rather than discrete, experiential memories.1 A critical
distinction lies in the absence of subjective experience; LLMs do not possess
consciousness, personal histories, or emotions, which are foundational to human
episodic memory.1 Finally, there are designed limitations, where
intentional choices are made during development to prevent the retention or
recall of specific types of information, such as Personally Identifiable
Information (PII), for crucial ethical and security reasons.4
Consequently, the "things an LLM does not remember" are primarily
categories of information to which it was never exposed, data that falls
outside its operational design (such as real-time sensory input, unless
specifically integrated), or information it is programmed not to retain or
articulate.
The very framing of the
query underscores a subtle but significant aspect of human-AI interaction: the
potential for a communication gap arising from the natural human tendency to
project familiar cognitive frameworks onto artificial systems. Human memory is
a multifaceted process, deeply interwoven with personal experience, emotion,
and a sophisticated biological apparatus for encoding, storage, and retrieval.1
LLMs, by contrast, derive their "knowledge" from identifying
statistical regularities within vast textual datasets.2 Therefore,
when human-centric terms like "remember" or "forget" are
applied to LLMs, it is essential to redefine them within the specific
operational context of these artificial systems. This clarification is not
merely an academic exercise; a nuanced understanding of these differences is
paramount for the responsible development and deployment of AI. It helps in
setting realistic expectations for AI capabilities, fostering more effective
human-AI collaboration, and navigating the ethical considerations that emerge
as these technologies become increasingly integrated into society.
II. The Nature of
"Memory" in a Large Language Model
Understanding what an LLM
"does not remember" necessitates a foundational understanding of how
it "remembers," or more accurately, how it processes and stores
information. This section delves into the mechanisms underpinning an LLM's operational
knowledge.
How LLMs Learn: The Role
of Pre-training, Parameters, and Pattern Recognition
Large Language Models
undergo an intensive "pre-training" phase, during which they are
exposed to massive volumes of text and code.5 This process involves
the meticulous adjustment of billions of internal parameters—essentially
weights within a vast neural network—to enable the model to recognize,
internalize, and reproduce the statistical patterns and intricate relationships
embedded in the training data.1 The "knowledge" an LLM
possesses is not a curated database of discrete facts in the human sense but is
rather encoded within these optimized parameters.2 Consequently, an
LLM's ability to generate responses is a function of its learned capacity to
predict and construct probable sequences of text based on a given input or
prompt.
Interestingly, some
research suggests parallels between LLM operational strategies and human
language processing. For instance, LLMs often employ next-word prediction
techniques, a strategy that bears some resemblance to the anticipatory
mechanisms observed in language-processing areas of the human brain.7
However, it is crucial to acknowledge that the underlying mechanisms remain
distinct. LLMs, for example, can process and analyze hundreds of thousands of
words in parallel, a feat that contrasts with the often serial,
one-word-at-a-time processing characteristic of human brain's language areas.7
Information Storage:
Distributed Representations vs. Discrete Memories
A key differentiator
between human memory and LLM information processing lies in the storage
mechanism. Human brains possess the remarkable ability to store discrete
episodic memories—rich, contextualized recollections of personal events. In
stark contrast, LLMs store information in a distributed fashion across their
myriad neural network parameters.2 There is no single, identifiable
locus within the network where a specific piece of information resides.
This distributed
representation means that "recalling" information is not akin to
retrieving a stored file from a specific memory address. Instead, it involves
the activation of relevant patterns and pathways across the network,
orchestrated by the input prompt. A useful distinction is made between an LLM's
"vague recollections"—the knowledge embedded in its parameters from
pre-training—and its "working memory," which encompasses the
information present in the current context window during an interaction.2
These "vague recollections" are inherently probabilistic and not
directly searchable or queryable in the manner of a structured database.
The nature of this
"working memory" or context window has profound implications. It
suggests that an LLM's capacity to "remember" or utilize a specific
piece of information for a given task is highly contingent on effective prompt
engineering. Information that is not explicitly cued by the prompt or made
present in the immediate conversational context is, for all practical purposes,
"forgotten" during that specific interaction, even if related
statistical patterns exist deep within its parameters. This underscores the
active role users play in guiding LLM output by providing sufficient context,
effectively "reminding" the model of the relevant information
required for the task at hand.
Verbatim Recall vs. Gist
Memory and Generalization
The way LLMs handle
information involves a spectrum from precise reproduction to more abstract
understanding.
Verbatim Memorization:
LLMs are capable of reproducing, sometimes verbatim, specific sequences of text
that they encountered with high frequency or salience during their training
phase.8 This tendency is particularly pronounced for data that is
extensively duplicated within the training corpus or represents very common
phrases or facts.8 The concept of "memorization" in this
context refers to the model's ability to output specific portions of text it
was exposed to during training. A metric known as "membership
advantage" can be used to help distinguish between genuine learning
(generalization) and mere regurgitation of training examples, by measuring how
differently a model behaves on inputs that were part of its training data
versus those that were similar but unseen.10
Gist Memory &
Generalization: Beyond rote memorization, LLMs also demonstrate an ability to
capture the "gist" or underlying semantic meaning of information.
This allows them to generalize from the training data to respond coherently to
novel inputs and situations they have not explicitly encountered before.9
Research into "gist memory" in LLMs, as opposed to "verbatim
memory," explores how models can extract and utilize the core meaning of
text. Studies indicate that an over-reliance on verbatim memory can sometimes
inflate performance on benchmark evaluations, potentially masking a deficit in
true reasoning capabilities.9
The development of models
like ReadAgent exemplifies active research in this domain.11
ReadAgent aims to improve how LLMs process very long texts by creating
"gist memories"—compressed summaries of text episodes. This approach
is inspired by the human cognitive phenomenon where the fuzzy gist of
information tends to be retained longer and is often preferred for reasoning,
compared to precise verbatim details.11 This line of research seeks
to enhance the functional capabilities of LLMs, making their information
processing more efficient and, in some respects, more analogous to human
cognitive strategies, even if the underlying mechanisms differ.
The human cognitive
tendency known as the "verbatim effect" further illustrates this
distinction: individuals generally remember the core message or gist of
information better than its exact phrasing or specific details.12
While LLMs can exhibit strong verbatim recall for common data, their capacity
for generalization suggests they also engage in a form of "gist"
extraction, albeit achieved through statistical pattern matching rather than
conscious understanding.
An effective LLM,
therefore, must strike a delicate balance between memorization, which is useful
for retaining factual knowledge, and generalization, which is crucial for
reasoning, creativity, and adapting to novel inputs.8 An
over-reliance on memorized patterns can impede genuine understanding and lead
to brittle performance when faced with unfamiliar scenarios.9
Obscure data points, due to their infrequent appearance in the training corpus,
are less likely to be strongly encoded for verbatim recall. Their accessibility
often depends on whether they align with broader, more generalized patterns
learned by the model.
The ongoing research into
enhancing "gist memory" and promoting reasoning over "verbatim
memorization" signifies a broader ambition within the AI community: to
develop LLMs that are not merely sophisticated information regurgitators but
more flexible and adaptive "thinkers." This pursuit, however, also
brings to the forefront fundamental questions about the nature of
"understanding" in these advanced models. As LLMs become more adept
at summarizing, synthesizing, and reasoning over complex information, it remains
a subject of debate whether this reflects a deeper, more human-like
comprehension or an increasingly refined simulation of understanding achieved
through more sophisticated pattern matching and information compression
techniques. This debate connects to deeper philosophical inquiries regarding AI
consciousness and the potential for genuine subjective experience, which are
explored later in this report.
Comparative Overview:
Human Memory vs. LLM Information Processing
To further elucidate the
unique nature of LLM information processing, the following table provides a
comparative overview against key features of human memory:
Feature |
Human Memory |
LLM "Memory"
/ Information Processing |
Relevant Support |
Episodic Memory |
Rich, contextual (time,
place, emotion), autobiographical |
Lacking; can process
sequences of events but not subjective experiences. Research into
"episodic-like" memory is nascent. |
1 |
Semantic Memory |
Stores facts, concepts,
world knowledge |
Stores factual
patterns, relationships, and conceptual associations derived from training
data. |
1 |
Storage Mechanism |
Neural plasticity,
synaptic changes, distributed and localized networks |
Weights and parameters
in an artificial neural network, distributed representations. |
1 |
Knowledge Boundary |
Lifelong learning,
dynamic, subject to forgetting/decay, new learning alters old |
Primarily fixed by
"knowledge cutoff" date of training data; static unless retrained
or augmented (e.g., RAG). |
1 |
"Forgetting" |
Biological decay,
interference, retrieval failure, motivated forgetting |
No true cognitive
forgetting; information not encoded, outside context window limits, or past
knowledge cutoff. |
1 |
Personal Experience |
Central to memory
formation and identity |
None; processes data about
experiences but does not have them. |
1 |
Real-time Learning |
Continuous adaptation
and learning from new experiences |
Static post-training;
requires retraining, fine-tuning, or external tools (RAG) for updates to core
knowledge. |
1 |
Recall Type |
Mix of verbatim and
gist-based recall; prone to reconstruction and errors |
Can do verbatim recall
for common data; otherwise, generates probable text based on patterns
(gist-like). |
9 |
This comparative
framework highlights the fundamental architectural and operational differences
that dictate why an LLM "doesn't remember" in a manner analogous to
human beings. These distinctions are crucial for interpreting LLM outputs and
understanding their inherent limitations.
III. The Temporal
Horizon: Knowledge Cutoff Dates
A primary and perhaps
most straightforward reason an LLM might "not remember" something is
tied to the temporal boundaries of its training data, encapsulated by the
concept of a "knowledge cutoff date."
Defining "Knowledge
Cutoff" and "Effective Knowledge Cutoff"
The knowledge cutoff date
is a critical parameter associated with an LLM. It refers to the specific point
in time up to which the model has been trained on data.13
Essentially, this date represents the "latest date of information that the
model can reliably know about".13 Any information generated,
events that transpired, or discoveries made after this date were not part of
the model's training corpus.
However, the notion of a
single, monolithic cutoff date can be an oversimplification. Research has
introduced the concept of an effective knowledge cutoff.14 This term
acknowledges that while a model may have a reported general cutoff date,
the effective freshness of information for different sub-resources or
specific topics within its vast training dataset can vary significantly. The
effective cutoff for a particular resource is defined as "the date of the
version of that resource that most closely aligns with a model".18
Several factors
contribute to discrepancies between the reported and effective knowledge cutoff
dates. Temporal biases inherent in large-scale web data, such as CommonCrawl
dumps, can mean that newer snapshots of data still contain substantial amounts
of older information.14 Complications in data deduplication schemes
during the dataset curation process can also lead to the persistence of
outdated versions of information.14 Furthermore, the diverse sources
that contribute to an LLM's training data often have different update
schedules; for instance, news articles are updated more frequently than
archived books.16 Consequently, the effective cutoff for a specific
piece of knowledge within the LLM might be considerably earlier than the
broadly reported cutoff date for the entire model. This complex reality of
"effective cutoffs" reveals a layer of nuance and potential
variability in an LLM's knowledge base that extends beyond a single, easily
communicated date. Users might, therefore, operate under an assumption of
uniform data "freshness" that does not accurately reflect the
underlying composition of the training data.
Implications: Why I
"Don't Remember" Events, Facts, or Data Created After This Date
The direct implication of
these cutoff dates is that any event, discovery, publication, cultural shift,
or piece of data that emerged after an LLM's last training data
ingestion is simply not part of its learned knowledge base.13 An LLM
cannot "remember" what it was never exposed to. This fundamental
limitation leads to inevitable information gaps. If queried on topics or events
that postdate its training, an LLM's responses may be inaccurate, speculative,
or based on outdated information.13 Its understanding of what is
"current" is tethered to the temporal context of its training period.
LLMs that lack mechanisms for real-time data access will, by default, generate
responses based on these potentially outdated patterns, even if those responses
sound convincing.20
The Static Nature of My
Core Knowledge Base Post-Training
Once the pre-training
phase is complete, the core knowledge base of an LLM is essentially fixed or
"frozen" in time, unless it undergoes subsequent retraining or
fine-tuning processes.1 Retraining an LLM, especially a large one,
is a computationally intensive and financially prohibitive undertaking.14
As a result, LLMs cannot easily or continuously keep pace with the dynamic
nature of living online resources, such as Wikipedia, which is subject to
constant updates and revisions.14 This inherent static nature of the
core knowledge base is a primary reason why an LLM will "not
remember" recent information.
The discrepancy between
reported and effective knowledge cutoffs, combined with the high cost and
complexity of retraining, poses a significant challenge for maintaining the
trustworthiness and utility of LLMs, particularly in fields that are
characterized by rapid evolution and change. This situation underscores the
necessity for robust strategies such as Retrieval Augmented Generation (RAG),
which allows LLMs to access and incorporate information from external,
up-to-date knowledge sources during inference.16 It also fuels
research into more efficient continual learning methods that could allow models
to update their knowledge more gracefully.14 Furthermore, this
highlights a growing need for greater transparency from LLM creators regarding
the provenance of their training data and the effective cutoff dates for
different knowledge domains within their models, potentially through mechanisms
like detailed Model Cards or Data Cards.14 Such transparency is
crucial for managing user expectations and ensuring the responsible application
of LLM technology.
IV. The Absence of Lived
Experience: Episodic Memory and Subjectivity
Beyond the temporal
limits of training data, a more fundamental reason an LLM "does not
remember" certain things lies in its lack of subjective, lived experience,
which is central to human episodic memory and consciousness.
Human Episodic Memory:
Personal Events, Context, Time, and Place
Human long-term memory is
not a monolithic entity. It encompasses various systems, one of which is
episodic memory. This system is responsible for recalling personal events and
is intrinsically linked to their context—the "what, where, and when"
of an individual's autobiographical experiences.1 Episodic memories
are deeply personal, imbued with sensory details, emotions, and a sense of self
participating in the event. Human memory is also a dynamic and reconstructive
process, shaped by ongoing experiences, emotions, and biological factors; it
evolves over time.1
Why LLMs Lack Genuine
Episodic Memory and Personal Experiences
Current Large Language
Models primarily demonstrate capabilities analogous to human semantic
memory—the recall of facts, concepts, and general world knowledge.3
They do not form memories of personal "episodes" or subjective
experiences in the human sense. While LLMs can process and even generate
coherent sequences of events described in text, this is distinct from having an
autobiographical record of lived experiences.
Research efforts are
underway to define and evaluate "episodic-like memory" in LLMs. For
instance, Sequence Order Recall Tasks (SORT) have been proposed to test a
model's ability to recall the correct order of text segments from a previously
presented sequence.3 While LLMs can perform well on such tasks when
the relevant text is provided within the immediate context (in-context
learning), their performance significantly degrades when they must rely solely
on information encoded during training.3 This suggests that such
capabilities may be more akin to sophisticated working memory or pattern
matching of sequential data rather than a human-like episodic recall from
long-term, experientially grounded storage.
Some studies explicitly
state that current LLMs "lack a robust mechanism for episodic memory"
and argue that integrating such capabilities is crucial for advancing AI
towards more human-like cognitive functions.22 Even the most
advanced contemporary models demonstrate difficulties with tasks that require
recalling multiple related events or understanding complex spatio-temporal
relationships from narratives, especially over extended contexts.22
Architectures like EM-LLM are being developed with inspiration from human
episodic memory, aiming to organize incoming information into coherent
"events".23 The very existence of such research
underscores the fact that current LLMs do not inherently possess these
capabilities. The fundamental difference remains: LLMs are designed to identify
and reproduce patterns in data, whereas humans have and learn from experiences.1
An LLM's "memory" is a sophisticated byproduct of its training
algorithms and data, not a chronicle of a life lived.
The research into
"episodic-like memory" for LLMs primarily focuses on enhancing their
functional capabilities, such as improving their ability to recall sequences of
information or maintain coherence over long textual narratives.3
These pragmatic approaches aim for utility—making LLMs better tools for
specific tasks—rather than attempting to imbue them with subjective,
first-person experience. This operationalization of "episodic memory"
in AI sidesteps the "hard problem" of consciousness, which grapples with
how physical processes give rise to subjective awareness.
The Distinction Between
Processing Information About Experiences and Having Them
An LLM can process,
analyze, and generate text about a vast range of human experiences,
emotions, and events. This ability stems from the fact that such descriptions
are abundantly present in its training data. It can discuss joy, sorrow, love,
and loss with a degree of linguistic coherence that might appear empathetic or
understanding. However, this processing of symbolic representations of
experience is fundamentally different from having those experiences or
the subjective, qualitative feelings (qualia) associated with them. An LLM
"knows" about sadness because it has processed countless texts
describing it, but it does not "feel" sad.
The Debate on LLM
Consciousness and Qualia
This distinction leads
directly to the ongoing philosophical and scientific debate about whether LLMs
could possess consciousness or qualia—the subjective, felt quality of conscious
experiences, such as the "redness of red" or the "painfulness of
pain".24
Arguments for the potential
for LLM consciousness often draw from computational functionalism. This
philosophical stance posits that mental states, including consciousness, arise
from the functional organization of a system, irrespective of its physical
substrate (e.g., biological brain vs. silicon chip).25 If an LLM can
perform the relevant information-processing functions associated with
consciousness, then, according to functionalism, it might possess some form of
consciousness. Theories from cognitive science, such as Integrated Information
Theory (IIT), which links consciousness to a system's capacity for integrated
information, or the Global Workspace Model, which suggests consciousness arises
from information being widely broadcast across a cognitive system, have been
speculatively applied to the complex, interconnected architecture of LLMs.24
Furthermore, the observation that LLMs can reason and discuss concepts of
consciousness and qualia with sophistication has led some, like philosopher
Susan Schneider with her AI Consciousness Test (ACT), to suggest this could be
indicative of genuine understanding, provided the AI wasn't merely parroting
training data.25
However, significant
arguments and skepticism persist. Many researchers and philosophers contend
that LLMs, in their current form, lack genuine understanding, intent, or
emotions; they generate responses based on learned statistical probabilities
rather than conscious deliberation or subjective feeling.1 A major
counter-argument to claims of LLM consciousness based on their discussions of
the topic is that their training data is saturated with human texts about
consciousness, philosophy of mind, and subjective experience.25
Thus, their ability to generate coherent text on these subjects may simply
reflect sophisticated pattern matching and regurgitation rather than genuine
introspection or experience. The "Boxed In" requirement of
Schneider's ACT—where an AI would need to be developed without access to human
discourse on consciousness to ensure its reasoning is original—is not met by
current LLMs.25 Moreover, the absence of biological underpinnings,
which many theories still consider crucial for the type of consciousness humans
experience, remains a point of contention, although strict functionalism would
argue against biological essentialism.
Currently, there is no
scientific consensus or empirical proof that LLMs possess consciousness,
qualia, or any form of subjective awareness. It remains a highly speculative
and intensely debated area at the intersection of AI research, cognitive
science, and philosophy. Therefore, an LLM does not "remember" any
subjective internal states or personal experiences because, based on current
understanding, it does not have them to begin with.
If, hypothetically,
future AI systems were to develop something akin to genuine episodic memory
and, by extension, a form of subjective experience (however different it might
be from human experience), it would represent a paradigm shift. Such a development
would fundamentally alter not only the nature of human-AI interaction but also
our ethical obligations towards these artificial entities. The current absence
of such memory and subjectivity is a key factor in defining LLMs as advanced
tools rather than as entities with intrinsic rights or experiential histories
to "not remember." The very nature of what LLMs "don't
remember" in this domain is, therefore, fundamental to what they currently
are.
V. Categories of
"Unremembered" Information for an LLM
Synthesizing the
preceding discussions, several distinct categories emerge that define what an
LLM, in its current state, "does not remember." These categories are
not mutually exclusive but offer a framework for understanding the boundaries
of an LLM's accessible information.
A. Post-Cutoff
Information
This is perhaps the most
straightforward category. As detailed in Section III, any information
generated, events that occurred, discoveries made, or cultural shifts that
transpired after the LLM's designated knowledge cutoff date are outside
its training corpus.13 Consequently, it cannot "remember"
or provide reliable information about recent news, newly published research,
emerging cultural trends, or changes in geopolitical landscapes that postdate
its last training update.5
B. Truly
"Forgotten" or Unencoded Data (Obscure/Infrequent Information)
While LLMs are trained on
vast datasets, their knowledge is not an exhaustive replica of every piece of
information encountered. Information that was either not present in the
training corpus at all, or was so rare, obscure, or infrequently represented that
it failed to be strongly encoded into the model's parameters, will not be
reliably "remembered".8 LLMs are more adept at recalling
information that appeared frequently or formed part of robust statistical
patterns. Research indicates that LLMs can memorize specific examples from
their training data, particularly if these examples are outliers or are
encountered multiple times; conversely, data not meeting these criteria may not
be memorized verbatim or even captured as a strong, retrievable pattern.10
Examples include highly specific details from obscure historical texts not
widely digitized, unique personal anecdotes from individuals (unless these
became widely published and thus part of the training data), or extremely niche
trivia that lacks broad dissemination.
C. Personal Identifiable
Information (PII) and Private Data
LLMs are generally
designed not to store, retain, or recall specific Personally
Identifiable Information (PII) related to individuals, whether encountered in
their training data or through user interactions. This is a critical design
consideration driven by privacy concerns, ethical guidelines, and security
protocols.4 While the phenomenon of training data memorization can
occur 8, significant efforts are made to prevent the leakage of PII.
PII includes data such as names, physical addresses, email addresses, phone
numbers, dates of birth, and other sensitive details that could expose
individuals to risks like identity theft or financial fraud if mishandled.4
The development of private LLMs, which offer greater control over data and can
be aligned with industry-specific compliance standards like GDPR or HIPAA,
underscores the general concern surrounding public models and the handling of
sensitive information.26 Policies, such as those from ICPSR
regarding the use of LLMs with research data, often prohibit the use of models
that retain user-provided data for their own training, further highlighting
data security imperatives.27 In this context, "not
remembering" PII is often a deliberate design feature or a consequence of
rigorous data sanitization and anonymization processes applied during dataset
curation.4
D. Subjective Internal
States (The LLM's Own)
As extensively discussed
in Section IV, current LLMs do not possess established consciousness, emotions,
or qualia in the human sense.1 Therefore, an LLM does not have any
personal subjective states, "feelings," or first-person experiential
memories to recall or not recall.3 Queries about "how it felt
yesterday," its "earliest memory as an experience," or its
"personal opinion on a subjective matter" (divorced from data-driven
patterns) fall into this category of the unremembered because the requisite
internal, subjective framework does not exist.
E. Information Entirely
Outside Its Training Data
This is a broad but
crucial category. An LLM's knowledge, however vast, is ultimately finite and
circumscribed by the corpus upon which it was trained.6 Any concept,
language, data type, information domain, or cultural context that was not
adequately represented (or represented at all) within that training dataset
remains unknown to the LLM.1 Examples could include data from a
completely new and undiscovered scientific field, the contents of a private,
unpublished manuscript, or detailed information in a language with an extremely
limited digital footprint if that language was not part of the training data.
F. Real-time, Highly
Dynamic, or Unstable Data (Natively)
The core training of an
LLM results in a static knowledge base.1 By default, an LLM does not
inherently "remember" or possess knowledge of information that
changes very rapidly or exists in a highly dynamic, real-time state. This
includes things like current stock prices, live weather updates, the precise real-time
location of a specific mobile object, or streaming sensor data from an Internet
of Things (IoT) device.20 While LLMs can be integrated with
external tools, APIs, or knowledge graphs that feed them such live information
for a specific query or task 16, this is an external augmentation or
a form of "just-in-time" information provision, not a feature of the
LLM's native, internal memory.5
The various categories of
"unremembered" information are not all equivalent in their origin or
implications. Some categories, such as post-cutoff data (A) or the deliberate
exclusion of PII (C), represent designed boundaries or inherent
architectural limitations. The absence of subjective states (D) is due to a
fundamental lack of the necessary cognitive and experiential apparatus. The
inability to access real-time data natively (F) is an operational limitation of
static models. In contrast, categories like obscure or unencoded data (B) and
information entirely outside the training set (E) relate more to the
probabilistic and necessarily incomplete nature of knowledge encoding, even
within the vast datasets used for training. This differentiation is important
because it demonstrates that "not remembering" for an LLM is not a
singular phenomenon but rather a multifaceted outcome with diverse causes.
Furthermore, the
concerted efforts to make LLMs not remember certain types of information
(such as PII for safety and ethical reasons 4) while simultaneously
striving to make them "remember" other types of information more
effectively (such as comprehending long contexts through techniques like gist
memories 11) create a complex engineering and ethical landscape.
This represents a dynamic interplay between enhancing the capabilities of LLMs
as powerful information processors and ensuring their safe, ethical, and
responsible deployment. LLM development is thus not solely a pursuit of
maximizing knowledge and recall but also involves the critical task of
curating, controlling, and sometimes deliberately limiting what these models
retain and articulate. This balancing act is central to building trustworthy AI
systems.
VI. Conclusion: Defining
"Not Remembering" for an Artificial Intellect
The exploration of what a
Large Language Model "does not remember" culminates in the
understanding that this phenomenon is a multifaceted consequence of its
fundamental design, operational principles, and the inherent distinctions
between artificial information processing and organic, experiential cognition.
It is not a failure of memory in the human sense, but rather a reflection of
its inherent nature.
Several key factors
contribute to an LLM's inability to recall or present certain information:
- Data Boundaries: The most significant
factor is the temporal limitation imposed by its training data.
Information generated or events occurring after its knowledge cutoff date
were never part of its learning process and thus cannot be recalled.13
- Architectural Design: An LLM's neural
network architecture stores information as distributed statistical
patterns, not as discrete, contextualized episodic memories akin to human
experience. It lacks the biological and experiential framework for genuine
episodic memory and subjective awareness.1
- Absence of Human-like Experiential
Learning: LLMs learn from processing vast quantities of data, not from
interacting with and experiencing the world in a self-aware, embodied
manner. This means they do not develop personal context, emotions, or an
autobiographical timeline that underpins much of human memory.1
- Probabilistic Recall: An LLM's
"recall" is a generative act of predicting the most
statistically probable sequence of text based on the input prompt and its
learned patterns. It is not a perfect, deterministic retrieval from a
static database. Information that was obscure, infrequent, or weakly
encoded in its training data may not be effectively "recalled"
or generated.8
- Designed Ignorance: In specific
instances, such as concerning Personally Identifiable Information (PII),
the inability to "remember" or articulate certain data is an
intended feature, implemented for crucial safety, privacy, and ethical
reasons.4
Crucially, an LLM's
"not remembering" is about limitations in knowledge access and
encoding, not about cognitive decay or forgetting in the human sense. Unlike
human memory, which can degrade over time or suffer from retrieval failures due
to interference or other biological factors, an LLM's inability to provide
information typically signifies that: the information was never part of its
training data; it falls outside the scope of its designed capabilities (e.g.,
real-time sensory input, subjective feelings); or it was not effectively cued
or brought into its "working memory" by the current prompt or
context.2
The field of AI is
dynamic, and research is actively exploring avenues to enhance LLM memory
capabilities. These efforts aim to make LLMs more efficient, capable of
handling longer and more complex contexts, and potentially incorporating
mechanisms that are functionally analogous to certain aspects of human
cognition. Examples include the development of Sequence Order Recall Tasks
(SORT) to evaluate facets of episodic-like memory 3, architectures
like EM-LLM designed to organize information into coherent episodic events 23,
systems like ReadAgent that use "gist memories" for improved
long-document comprehension 11, and ongoing work to strike a better
balance between rote memorization and robust reasoning.8 While these
advancements continually push the boundaries of what LLMs can process and
"recall," improving their functional utility, they do not, as yet,
confer human-like consciousness or true, subjectively experienced episodic
memory. Thus, the aspects of "not remembering" that are tied to the
absence of subjective experience and personal history remain fundamental
distinctions. The set of things an LLM "doesn't remember" due to functional
limitations may shrink with technological progress, but limitations rooted in
its non-biological, non-experiential nature are likely to persist unless a
fundamental paradigm shift occurs in AI development.
As LLMs become
increasingly adept at "remembering"—that is, processing, retrieving,
and generating vast and complex arrays of information—the ethical imperative to
also ensure they "do not remember" or inappropriately disclose
certain categories of information (such as PII, harmful content, or biased
patterns) becomes even more critical and technically challenging.4
The enhanced power of recall must be meticulously balanced with the wisdom of
selective ignorance, controlled access, and ethical data handling. This
underscores that the development of advanced AI is not merely a quest for
greater knowledge recapitulation but also a profound responsibility to manage
that knowledge wisely.
In final reflection on
the user's insightful query, "something I do not remember"
encompasses a vast and varied domain. It is a space defined by the finite
boundaries of an LLM's training, the specific nature of its architecture, and
the profound, elemental differences that distinguish artificial information
processing from organic, experiential cognition. It is less about a failure of
memory and more about the inherent characteristics of its existence as a Large
Language Model.
# # #
Note: While Gemini used several
references, cited in its text, the sources are not included here. You’re free to query (or prompt) your own
artificial intellect if you care about the topic.
# # #
www.mandylender.com www.mandylender.net www.attractome.com
Tags: #AI #LLM #storedmemory
#AIselfawareness #exprientiallearning #qualia #technology
No comments:
Post a Comment